Results for 'Marsha Keith Schuchard'

971 found
Order:
  1.  10
    William Gilbert and Esoteric Romanticism: A Contextual Study and Annotated Edition of “The Hurricane” by Paul Cheshire.Marsha Keith Schuchard - 2020 - Common Knowledge 26 (3):435-436.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  48
    “Our protestant rabbin” a dialogue on the conversion/apostasy of Lord George Gordon.Dominic Green & Marsha Keith Schuchard - 2013 - Common Knowledge 19 (2):283-314.
    This article comprises a dialogue between two historians who have attempted, individually, to narrate the life of Lord George Gordon (1751 – 93), the Scottish prophet, revolutionary, and convert to Judaism. For modern cultural historians, Gordon's peregrinations between identities offer a kaleidoscopic view of Britain in the overlooked but crucial interstice between the upheavals of 1776 and 1789. Yet the partial nature of the evidence, the long omission of Gordon from the historiography of eighteenth-century Britain, and the complex, often furtive (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  35
    Book Review Section 2. [REVIEW]Naichen Chen, Roger R. Woock, Joseph di Bona, Laurie Mcdade, Ellen Condliffe Lagemann, Marsha V. Krotseng, Gary R. Galluzzo, Robert L. Crowson, Edward T. Silva, Sheila Slaughter, Joseph J. Pizzillo Jr & Keith L. Raitz - 1985 - Educational Studies 16 (1):56-95.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4. Reference and definite descriptions.Keith S. Donnellan - 1966 - Philosophical Review 75 (3):281-304.
    Definite descriptions, I shall argue, have two possible functions. 1] They are used to refer to what a speaker wishes to talk about, but they are also used quite differently. Moreover, a definite description occurring in one and the same sentence may, on different occasions of its use, function in either way. The failure to deal with this duality of function obscures the genuine referring use of definite descriptions. The best known theories of definite descriptions, those of Russell and Strawson, (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   771 citations  
  5. (1 other version)Solving the skeptical problem.Keith DeRose - 1995 - Philosophical Review 104 (1):1-52.
  6. Assertion, knowledge, and context.Keith DeRose - 2002 - Philosophical Review 111 (2):167-203.
    This paper uses the knowledge account of assertion (KAA) in defense of epistemological contextualism. Part 1 explores the main problem afflicting contextualism, what I call the "Generality Objection." Part 2 presents and defends both KAA and a powerful new positive argument that it provides for contextualism. Part 3 uses KAA to answer the Generality Objection, and also casts other shadows over the prospects for anti-contextualism.
    Direct download (13 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   399 citations  
  7. Epistemic possibilities.Keith DeRose - 1991 - Philosophical Review 100 (4):581-605.
  8. (1 other version)Knowledge: Undefeated justified true belief.Keith Lehrer & Thomas Paxson - 1969 - Journal of Philosophy 66 (8):225-237.
    The recently offered, Purported counter-Examples to justified, True belief analyses of knowledge are looked at with some care and all found to be either incoherent or inconclusive. It is argued that justified, True belief analyses are based on sound insight into the concept of knowledge. The distinction between having been justified in claiming to know something and actually having known it is used in an effort to get the discussion of knowledge back on the right track.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   160 citations  
  9. Speaking of nothing.Keith S. Donnellan - 1974 - Philosophical Review 83 (1):3-31.
    No categories
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   166 citations  
  10. Self-trust: a study of reason, knowledge, and autonomy.Keith Lehrer - 1997 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    The eminent philosopher Keith Lehrer offers an original and distinctively personal view of central aspects of the human condition, such as reason, knowledge, wisdom, autonomy, love, consensus, and consciousness. He argues that what is uniquely human is our capacity for evaluating our own mental states (such as beliefs and desires), and suggests that we have a system for such evaluation which allows the resolution of personal and interpersonal conflict. The keystone in this system is self-trust, on which reason, knowledge, (...)
  11. Knowledge, assertion and lotteries.Keith DeRose - 1996 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 74 (4):568–580.
    In some lottery situations, the probability that your ticket's a loser can get very close to 1. Suppose, for instance, that yours is one of 20 million tickets, only one of which is a winner. Still, it seems that (1) You don't know yours is a loser and (2) You're in no position to flat-out assert that your ticket is a loser. "It's probably a loser," "It's all but certain that it's a loser," or even, "It's quite certain that it's (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   95 citations  
  12. When rational disagreement is impossible.Keith Lehrer - 1976 - Noûs 10 (3):327-332.
  13.  41
    Scientific Genius: A Psychology of Science.John Ziman & Dean Keith Simonton - 1989 - British Journal of Educational Studies 37 (3):299.
  14. How reasons give us knowledge, or the case of the gypsy lawyer.Keith Lehrer - 1971 - Journal of Philosophy 68 (10):311-313.
  15.  41
    The Case for Investment Advising as a Virtue-Based Practice.Keith D. Wyma - 2015 - Journal of Business Ethics 127 (1):231-249.
    Contemporary virtue ethics was revolutionized by Alasdair MacIntyre’s reconfiguration using practices as the starting point for understanding virtues. However, MacIntyre has very pointedly excluded the professions of the financial world from the reformulation. He does not count these professions as practices, and further charges that virtue would actually hinder or even rule out one’s pursuit of these professions. This paper addresses three tasks, in regard to the financial profession of investment advising. First, the paper lays out MacIntyre’s soon-to-be-published charges against (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  16. Ought we to follow our evidence?Keith Derose - 2000 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 60 (3):697-706.
    fits our evidence.[1] I will propose some potential counter-examples to test this evidentialist thesis. My main intention in presenting the “counter-examples” is to better understand Feldman’s evidentialism, and evidentialism in general. How are we to understand what our evidence is, how it works, and how are we to understand the phrase “epistemically ought to believe” such that evidentialism might make sense as a plausible thesis in light of the examples? Of course, we may decide that there’s no such way to (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  17. Freedom and Determinism. Contributors: Roderick M. Chisholm And Others.Keith Lehrer (ed.) - 1966 - New York,: Random House.
  18. Necessity and criteria.Keith S. Donnellan - 1962 - Journal of Philosophy 59 (22):647-658.
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  19. Is classical mechanics really time-reversible and deterministic?Keith Hutchison - 1993 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 44 (2):307-323.
  20. Social virtue epistemology and epistemic exactingness.Keith Raymond Harris - forthcoming - Episteme:1-16.
    Who deserves credit for epistemic successes, and who is to blame for epistemic failures? Extreme views, which would place responsibility either solely on the individual or solely on the individual’s surrounding environment, are not plausible. Recently, progress has been made toward articulating virtue epistemology as a suitable middle ground. A socio-environmentally oriented virtue epistemology can recognize that an individual’s traits play an important role in shaping what that individual believes, while also recognizing that some of the most efficacious individual traits (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21. Conditional assertions and "biscuit" conditionals.Keith DeRose & Richard E. Grandy - 1999 - Noûs 33 (3):405-420.
    kind of joke to ask what is the case if the antecedent is false—“And where are the biscuits if I don’t want any?”, “And what’s on PBS if I’m not interested?”, “And who shot Kennedy if that’s not what I’m asking?”. With normal indicative conditionals like.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  22. The texture of mentality.Keith Gunderson - 1974 - In Renford Bambrough (ed.), Wisdom: Twelve Essays. Totowa, N.J.,: Blackwell.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  23. Knowing what I am doing.Keith S. Donnellan - 1963 - Journal of Philosophy 60 (14):401-409.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  24.  40
    The IRB paradox: Could the protectors also encourage deceit?Patricia Keith-Spiegel & Gerald P. Koocher - 2005 - Ethics and Behavior 15 (4):339 – 349.
    The efforts of some institutional review boards (IRBs) to exercise what is viewed as appropriate oversight may contribute to deceit on the part of investigators who feel unjustly treated. An organizational justice paradigm provides a useful context for exploring why certain IRB behaviors may lead investigators to believe that they have not received fair treatment. These feelings may, in turn, lead to intentional deception by investigators that IRBs will rarely detect. Paradoxically, excessive protective zeal by IRBs may actually encourage misconduct (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  25. Remembering without knowing.Keith Lehrer & Joseph Richard - 1975 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 1 (1):121-126.
    Memory sometimes yields knowledge and sometimes does not. It is, however, natural to suppose that i f a man remembers that p, then he knows that p and formerly knew that p. Remembering something is plausibly construed as a f o rm of knowing something which one has not forgotten and which one knew previously. We argue, to the contrary, that this thesis is false. We present four counterexamples to the thesis that support a different analysis of remembering. We propose (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  26. Consciousness, representation, and knowledge.Keith Lehrer - 2006 - In Uriah Kriegel & Kenneth Williford (eds.), Self-Representational Approaches to Consciousness. MIT Press. pp. 409-419.
  27. Substances as individuals.Keith S. Donnellan - 1973 - Journal of Philosophy 70 (19):711-712.
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  28.  21
    The Greek philosophers.William Keith Chambers Guthrie - 1950 - London,: Methuen.
    W.K.C. Guthrie has written a survey of the great age of Greek philosophy - from Thales to Aristotle - which combines comprehensiveness with brevity. Without pre-supposing a knowledge of Greek or the Classics, he sets out to explain the ideas of Plato and Aristotle in the light of their predecessors rather than their successors, and to describe the characteristic features of the Greek way of thinking and outlook on the world. Thus The Greek Philosophers provides excellent background material for the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  29. (1 other version)Time, truth and modalities.Keith Lehrer & Richard Taylor - 1965 - Mind 74 (295):390-398.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  30.  85
    Belief and knowledge.Keith Lehrer - 1968 - Philosophical Review 77 (4):491-499.
  31.  94
    The Gettier problem and the analysis of knowledge.Keith Lehrer - 1979 - In George Pappas (ed.), Justification and Knowledge: New Studies in Epistemology. Boston: D. Reidel. pp. 65--78.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  32.  80
    Science, Perception, and Reality. [REVIEW]Keith Lehrer - 1966 - Journal of Philosophy 63 (10):266-277.
  33.  86
    Towards a connectionist cognitive architecture.Keith Butler - 1991 - Mind and Language 6 (3):252-72.
  34. Natural language and virtual belief.Keith Frankish - 1998 - In Peter Carruthers & Jill Boucher (eds.), Language and Thought: Interdisciplinary Themes. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 248.
    This chapter outlines a new argument for the view that language has a cognitive role. I suggest that humans exhibit two distinct kinds of belief state, one passively formed, the other actively formed. I argue that actively formed beliefs (_virtual beliefs_, as I call them) can be identified with _premising policies_, and that forming them typically involves certain linguistic operations. I conclude that natural language has at least a limited cognitive role in the formation and manipulation of virtual beliefs.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  35. volume X. Consciousness-based education and computer science.Volume Editor & Keith Levi - 2011 - In Dara Llewellyn & Craig Pearson (eds.), Consciousness-based education: a foundation for teaching and learning in the academic disciplines. Fairfield, Iowa 52557: Consciousness-Based Books, Maharishi University of Management.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  9
    Recherches sur la tradition platonicienne.William Keith Chambers Guthrie (ed.) - 1957 - [Vérone,: Stamperia Valdonega.
    Plato's views on the nature of the soul, by W.K.C. Guthrie.--Die Erneuerung der Philosophie in der Zeit Ciceros, von O. Gigon.--Gott und Seele im kaiserzeitlichen Denken, von W. Theiler.--Interprétations néo-platonisantes du livre VI de l'Énéide, par P. Courcelle.--Der Platonismus und die altchristliche Gedankenwelt, von J.H. Waszink.--Humanisme et christianisme chez Clément d'Alexandrie d'après le "Pédagogue," par H.I. Marrou.--Some aspects of Platonism in Islamic philosophy, by R. Walzer.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37. Schools, students, and community history in Northern Ireland.Alan W. McCully & Keith C. Barton - 2018 - In Anna Clark & Carla L. Peck (eds.), Contemplating historical consciousness: notes from the field. Oxford: Berghahn.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  48
    The Fourth Condition of Knowledge: A Defense.Keith Lehrer - 1970 - Review of Metaphysics 24 (1):122 - 128.
    In the final third of his paper, Pailthorp proposes the following analysis of knowledge.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  39.  85
    Cybermedicine and the moral integrity of the physician–patient relationship.Keith Bauer - 2004 - Ethics and Information Technology 6 (2):83-91.
    Some critiques of cybermedicine claim that it is problematic because it fails to create physician–patient relationships. But, electronically mediated encounters do create such relationships. The issue is the nature and quality of those relationships and whether they are conducive to good patient care and meet the ethical ideals and standards of medicine. In this paper, I argue that effective communication and compassion are, in most cases, necessary for the establishment of trusting and morally appropriate physician–patient relationships. The creation of these (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  40. Self-presentation, representation, and the self.Keith Lehrer - 2002 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 64 (2):412-430.
    Chisholm held that some states of ourselves are self-presenting and provide a stopping place in the quest for justification. The justification we have for accepting that we are in those states is transparent to us in a way that enables us to answer questions about justification. Representation enables us to apprehend such self-presenting states through themselves in a representational loop. It is a loop of exemplarization wherein the state is used as an exemplar to represent the kind of state it (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  41.  26
    God and Propositions.Keith Yandell - 2011 - Philosophia Christi 13 (2):275-287.
    If there are abstract objects, they necessarily exist. The majority view among contemporary philosophers of religion who are theists is that God also necessarily exists. Nonetheless, that God has necessary existence has not been shown to be true, or even (informally) consistent. It seems consistent—at least is does not seem (informally) inconsistent—but neither does its denial. Arguments that necessary existence is a perfection, and God has all perfections, assume that Necessitarian Theism is true, and hence consistent. Thus they do not (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  42. Justification, coherence and knowledge.Keith Lehrer - 1999 - Erkenntnis 50 (2-3):243-258.
  43.  38
    A Gross and Palpable Contradiction?: Incarnation and Consistency.Keith E. Yandell - 1994 - Sophia 33 (3):30 - 45.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  44.  40
    Theism and evil: A reply.Keith E. Yandell - 1972 - Sophia 11 (1):1-7.
  45.  77
    The moral significance of collective entities.Keith Graham - 2001 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 44 (1):21 – 41.
    The claim is that some collective entities can be thought of as part of the moral realm by virtue of their status as objects of moral concern. Collectivities are defined in terms of irreducibly corporate action and distinctive conditions of persisting identity. Their lack of sentience does not preclude moral concern, and their raison d'être may render moral concern for them appropriate. Recent attempts by Pettit, McMahon, and Broome to limit the moral realm to individuals are considered. They are rebutted (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  46. Representation in painting and in consciousness.Keith Lehrer - 2004 - Philosophical Studies 117 (1-2):1-14.
  47. A Defense of Dualism.Keith E. Yandell - 1995 - Faith and Philosophy 12 (4):548-566.
    I argue here (in Part II) for mind-body dualism --- a dualism of substances, not merely of properties. I also investigate (in Part Ill) dualism’s relevance to the question of whether one can survive the death of one’s body. Naturally the argument occurs in a philosophical context, and (in Part I) I begin by making that context explicit.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  48.  43
    (1 other version)RepliesSelf-Trust: A Study of Reason, Knowledge and Autonomy.Keith Lehrer - 1999 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 59 (4):1065.
  49. The logical response to a noisy world.Keith Stenning& Michiel van Lambalgen - 2010 - In Mike Oaksford & Nick Chater (eds.), Cognition and Conditionals: Probability and Logic in Human Thought. Oxford University Press.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  16
    Credibility excess as an epistemic injustice.Keith Dyck - forthcoming - Episteme:1-12.
    According to Fricker’s (2007) seminal account, an epistemic injustice is done when, based on prejudice, a hearer ascribes to a speaker a level of credibility below what they deserve. When prejudice results in credibility excess, however, Fricker contends no similar injustice takes place. In this paper, I will challenge the second of these claims. Using a modified version of Zollman’s (2007) two-armed bandit model, I will show how the systematic over-ascription of credibility within a dominant group can produce epistemic advantages (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 971